Vaibhāṣika


Sarvāstivāda-Vaibhāṣika or simply Vaibhāṣika, refers to an ancient Buddhist tradition of Abhidharma, which was very influential in north India, especially Kashmir. In various texts, they referred to their tradition as Yuktavāda, and another name for them was Hetuvāda. The Vaibhāṣika school was an influential subgroup of the larger Sarvāstivāda school. They were distinguished from other Sarvāstivāda sub-schools like the Sautrāntika and the "Western Masters" of Gandhara and Bactria by their orthodox adherence to the doctrines found in the Mahāvibhāṣa. Vaibhāṣika thought significantly influenced the Buddhist philosophy of all major Mahayana Buddhist schools of thought and also influenced the later forms of Theravāda Abhidhamma.
The Sarvāstivāda tradition arose in the Mauryan Empire during the second century BCE, and was possibly founded by Kātyānīputra. During the Kushan era, the "Great Commentary" on Abhidharma was compiled, marking the beginning of Vaibhāṣika as a proper school of thought. This tradition was well supported by Kanishka, and later spread throughout North India and Central Asia. It maintained its own canon of scriptures in Sanskrit, which included a seven-part Abhidharma Pitaka collection. Vaibhāṣika remained the most influential Buddhist school in northwest India from the first century CE until the seventh century.
Despite numerous variations and doctrinal disagreements within the tradition, most Sarvāstivāda-Vaibhāṣikas were united in their acceptance of the doctrine of "
sarvāstitva", which says that all phenomena in the three times can be said to exist. Another defining Vaibhāṣika doctrine was that of simultaneous causation, hence their alternative name of "Hetuvāda"''.

Canonical texts

The main source of this tradition is was the Sarvāstivāda Abhidharma Pitaka.
The texts of the Sarvāstivādin Abhidharma Pitaka are:
Together, these comprise the Six Treatises. The seventh text is the Jñānaprasthāna, also known as Aṣṭaskandha or Aṣṭagrantha, said to be composed by Kātyāyanīputra.Yaśomitra is said to have likened this text to the body of the above six treatises, referring to them as its legs.

Exegetical texts

The Jñānaprasthāna became the basis for Sarvastivada exegetical works called vibhāṣa, which were composed in a time of intense sectarian debate among the Sarvāstivādins in Kashmir. These compendia not only contain sutra references and reasoned arguments but also contain new doctrinal categories and positions. The most influential of these was the Abhidharma Mahāvibhāṣa Śāstra, a massive work which became the central text of the Vaibhāṣika tradition who became the Kasmiri Sarvāstivāda Orthodoxy under the patronage of the Kushan empire.
There are also two other extant Vibhasa compendia, though there is evidence for the existence of many more of these works which are now lost. The Vibhasasastra of Sitapani and the Abhidharmavibhasasastra translated by Buddhavarman c. 437 and 439 A.D. are the other extant Vibhasa works. Though some scholars claim the Mahāvibhāṣa dates to the reign of Kanishka during the first century CE, this dating is uncertain. However, we at least know it was translated into Chinese by the late 3rd or early 4th century.

Treatises

In addition to the canonical Sarvāstivādan Abhidharma, a variety of expository texts or treatises were written to serve as overviews and introductions to the Abhidharma. The best known belonging to the Sarvāstivāda tradition are:
The most mature and refined form of Vaibhāṣika philosophy can be seen in the work of master Saṃghabhadra , "undoubtedly one of the most brilliant Abhidharma masters in India". His two main works, the *Nyāyānusāra and the *Abhidharmasamayapradīpikā, are very important sources for late Vaibhāṣika thought. His work was referenced and cited by various important figures, such as Xuanzang and Sthiramati.

Dharmas

Dharmas and their characteristics

All Buddhist schools of Abhidharma divided up the world into "dharmas", which are the fundamental building blocks of all phenomenal experience. Unlike the sutras, the Abhidharma analyzes experience into these momentary psycho-physical processes. Dharmas refers to the discrete and impermanent instances of consciousness along with their intentional objects that rapidly arise and pass away in sequential streams. They are analogous to atoms, but are psycho-physical. Hence, according to Noa Ronkin, "all experiential events are understood as arising from the interaction of dharmas."
From the Vaibhāṣika perspective, "Abhi-dharma" refers to analyzing and understanding the nature of dharmas and the wisdom that arises from this. This systematic understanding of the Buddha's teaching was seen by Vaibhāṣikas as the highest expression of the Buddha's wisdom which was necessary to practice the Buddhist path. It is seen as representing the true intention of the Buddha on the level of absolute truth. According to the Mahāvibhāṣa, "abhidharma is the analysis of the intrinsic characteristics and common characteristics of dharmas."
For Vaibhāṣikas, dharmas are the "fundamental constituents of existence" which are discrete and real entities. K.L. Dhammajoti states:
A dharma is defined as that which holds its intrinsic characteristic. The intrinsic characteristic of the dharma called rūpa, for example, is the susceptibility of being molested, obstructability and visibility; that of another dharma called vedanā is sensation, etc. And for a dharma to be a dharma, its intrinsic characteristic must be sustainable throughout time: A rūpa remains as a rūpa irrespective of its various modalities. It can never be transformed into another different dharma. Thus, a uniquely characterizable entity is a uniquely real entity, having a unique intrinsic nature : “To be existent as an absolute entity is to be existent as an intrinsic characteristic.”
This idea is seen in the Jñānaprasthāna which states: "dharmas are determined with respect to nature and characteristic...Dharmas are determined, without being co-mingled. They abide in their intrinsic natures, and do not relinquish their intrinsic natures."
According to Vaibhāṣikas, the svabhāvas of dharmas are those things that exist substantially as opposed to those things which are made up of aggregations of dharmas and thus only have a nominal existence. This distinction is also termed the doctrine of the two truths, which holds that there is a conventional truth that refers to things which can be further analyzed, divided or broken up into smaller constituents and an ultimate truth referring to that which resists any further analysis.
Thus, a dharma's intrinsic characteristic and the very ontological existence of a dharma is one and the same. For the Vaibhāṣika school, this "own nature" was said to be the characteristic of a dharma that persists through the three times.
Vaibhāṣika Abhidharma also describes dharmas as having "common characteristics", which applies to numerous dharmas. Only the mental consciousness can cognize common characteristics.
However, the intrinsic characteristics of a dharma have a certain kind of relativity due to the relationship between various dharmas. For example, all rūpa dharmas have the common characteristic of resistance, but this is also an intrinsic characteristic with respect to other dharmas like vedanā.
Also, various sources state that the intrinsic nature of a dharma is "weak" and that they are interdependent with other dharmas. The Mahāvibhāṣa states that "conditioned dharmas are weak in their intrinsic nature, they can accomplish their activities only through mutual dependence" and that "they have no sovereignty. They are dependent on others." Thus, an intrinsic nature arises due to dependently originated processes or relationships between various dharmas and therefore, a svabhāva'' is not something which is completely ontologically independent.

Classification of dharmas

Abhidharma thought can be seen as an attempt at providing a complete account of every type of experience. Therefore an important part of Vaibhāṣika Abhidharma comprises the classification, definition and explanation of the different types of dharma as well as the analysis of conventional phenomena and how they arise from the aggregation of dharmas. Thus there is the element of dividing up things into their constituents as well as the element of synthesis, i.e. how dharmas combine to make up conventional things.
The Vaibhāṣikas made use of classic early Buddhist doctrinal categories such as the five skandhas, the sense bases and the "eighteen dhātus". Beginning with the Pañcavastuka of Vasumitra, the Vaibhāṣikas also adopted a five group classification of dharmas which outlined a total of 75 types of phenomena.
The five main classifications of dharmas are:
Dharmas are also classified and divided into further taxonomical categories providing further aids to understanding the Buddhist view and path. Some of the major ways that the Vaibhāṣikas classified dharmas include the following:
Matter is that which is "subject to deterioration or disintegration." As Vasubandhu says, it is what "is repeatedly molested/broken" by contact. The main way of defining matter for Vaibhāṣikas is that it has two main distinctive natures: resistance, which is “the hindrance to the arising of another thing in its own location,” and visibility, which allows one to locate matter since "it can be differently indicated as being here or being there".
The primary material dharmas are the four Great Elements — earth, water, fire, air. All other dharmas are "derived matter" which arise on the basis of the Great Realities. According to Dhammajoti: "The four Great Elements exist inseparably from one another, being co-existent causes one to another. Nevertheless, rūpa-dharma‑s are manifested and experienced in diverse forms because of the difference in intensity or substance of one or more of the four Elements."
Vaibhāṣika also had a theory of atoms. However, these atoms were not seen as eternally immutable or permanent and instead are seen as momentary. For Vaibhāṣika, an atom is the smallest unit of matter, which cannot be cut, broken up and has no parts. They come together to form aggregations or "molecules". They held that this is "known through mental analysis."

Mind and mental factors

In Vaibhāṣika Abhidharma, the mind is a real entity, which is referred to by three mostly synonymous terms: citta, manas and vijñāna, which are sometimes seen as different functional aspects of the mind. As defined by K.L. Dhammajoti, citta "is the general discernment or apprehension with respect to each individual object. This discernment is the mere grasping of the object itself, without apprehending any of its particularities." Saṃghabhadra defines it as what "grasps the characteristic of an object in a general manner."
Citta never arises by itself, it is always accompanied by certain mental factors or events, which are real and distinct dharmas that make a unique contribution to the mental process. Therefore, a moment of thought always has a specific nature and content. Cittas and caittas always arise together simultaneously in mutually dependent relationships.
The doctrine which said that these two always arise and operate together is called "conjunction". What conjunction meant was a disputed topic among the early masters. Later, it came to be accepted that for citta and caittas to be conjoined, the following had to be true: both must be supported by the same basis, they must have the same object, mode of activity, same time, and the same substance. This doctrine was repudiated by the Sautrāntika, who held that dharmas only arise successively, one after the other.
As seen in their list of dharmas, the Vaibhāṣikas classified caittas into various sub-categories based on various qualities. For example, the first classification, the universal dharmas, are so called because they exist in all types of citta. Then there are also universal good dharmas and universal defilements.
One of the major controversies in Abhidharma Buddhism dealt with the question of the original nature of citta. Some, like the Mahāsāṃghika, held the view that it retains an originally pure nature. Vaibhāṣikas like Saṃghabhadra rejected this view, holding that the nature of citta can also be defiled.

''Cittaviprayuktasaṃskāras''

Unlike other Abhidharma schools, the Vaibhāṣikas added another ultimate classification termed citta-viprayukta-saṃskāra, “conditionings disjoined from thought.” These "are real entities which are neither mental nor material in nature, which yet can operate on both domains" and can be seen as laws of nature. Dhammajoti notes however that the Abhidharma works of other schools like the *Śāriputrābhidharma also contain this category, just not as one of the main ultimate classifications. He also notes that there was never full agreement on how many dharmas are found in this category and that the Sautrāntikas did not accept their reality. Thus it was a much debated topic in Northern Abhidharma traditions.
Perhaps the most important of these conditionings are acquisition and non-acquisition. Acquisition:
Is a force that links a dharma to a particular serial continuity, i.e., the individual. Non-acquisition is another real entity whose function and nature are just opposed to those of acquisition: It acts to ensure that a given dharma is delinked from the individual serial continuity...It was at a relatively later stage that acquisition came to be defined generally as the dharma that effects the relation of any dharma to a living being.
These conditionings are particularly important because, due to their theory of tri-temporal existence, acquisition is central to the Vaibhāṣika understanding of defilement and purification. Since a defilement is a real dharma that exists always ; it cannot be destroyed, however it can be de-linked from an individual by disrupting the acquisition-series. This also helps to explain how one can obtain a pure dharma such as nirvāṇa, since it is only through acquisition that one experiences nirvāṇa.
Another doctrinally important set of conditionings are "the four characteristics of the conditioned." Dharmas are said to have the production-characteristic which allows them to arise, the duration-characteristic which is what enables it to temporarily remain and the decay-characteristic which is the force which impairs its activity so that it can no longer continue projecting another distinct effect. A dharma also has the impermanence or disappearance characteristic which is what causes it to enter into the past.

''Asaṃskṛta'' (the unconditioned)

Unconditioned dharmas are those which exist without being dependently co-arisen, they are also not temporal or spatial. They transcend arising and ceasing, and are real existents that possess a unique efficacy.
The Vaibhāṣika school taught three types of unconditioned dharmas: space, cessation through deliberation, and cessation independent of deliberation.
In the MVŚ, some disagreement among Sarvāstivāda masters regarding these dharmas can be seen. Some like "the Bhadanta" denied the reality of space. Meanwhile, Dārṣṭāntikas denied the ontological reality of all three.
According to Dhammajoti, cessation through deliberation refers to "the cessation of defilements acquired through the process of discriminative or deliberative effort." There are just as many of these cessations as there are with-outflow dharmas. Cessation independent of liberation meanwhile "are those acquired simply on account of the deficiency in the required assemblage of conditions for the particular dharma‑s. They are so called because they are independent of any deliberative effort." There are as many of these cessations are there are conditioned dharmas.
Cessation through deliberation is also the technical term for the Buddhist goal of nirvāṇa, which is also defined as "a disjunction from with-outflow dharma‑s acquired through the process of discrimination/deliberation which is a specific outflow-free prajñā." Nirvāṇa is the absolute absence of karma and the defilements, the escape from the skandhas and all saṃsāric existence which attained by an arhat.

Nirvāṇa's real existence

In Sarvāstivāda, nirvāṇa is a "distinct positive entity". It is "an ontologically real force that is acquired by the practitioner when a given defilement is completely abandoned." This force ensures that the defilement's acquisition will never arise again. Master Skandhila’s definition indicates how this real entity has a positive presence, which is said to be "like a dike holding back the water or a screen blocking the wind."
Vaibhāṣika holds that the real existence of nirvāṇa is supported both by direct perception and by scripture which depict the Buddha stating that "there is definitely the unborn." Sautrāntikas disagree with this interpretation of scripture, holding that the unborn simply refers to the discontinuity of birth, and thus it is a mere concept referring to the absence of suffering due to the abandoning of the defilements and thus it is only relatively real. However, Saṃghabhadra argues that "it is only when the unborn is conceded to be a distinct real entity that it is meaningful to say 'there is'. Besides, if there were no such entity, the Buddha should have simply said 'there is the discontinuity of the born.'"
According to Vaibhāṣika, nirvāṇa must be an ultimately real existent because no real supporting phenomena can be found which could serve as the basis on which to designate nirvāṇa as a relative existent. Also, if nirvāṇa is not a real force, then beings could not give rise to delight in nirvāṇa and disgust towards saṃsāra, for nirvāṇa would be inferior in terms of existence. It would also mean that the Buddha had been deluding everyone by speaking of non-existents in the same way that he spoke of the existents.
Furthermore, if nirvāṇa was unreal, it could not be one of the four noble truths, since a non-existent cannot be said to be true or false. An ārya is said to directly see the four truths, including the third truth of duḥkhanirodha and wisdom cannot arise with regard to a non-existent object.

Time and Ontology

Existence

The name Sarvāstivāda literally means "all exists", referring to their doctrine that all dharmas, past present and future, exist. This doctrine of tri-temporal existence has been described as an eternalist theory of time.
What does it mean for a dharma to exist? For the Sarvāstivāda Abhidharmikas, the main reasons that something is real or existent is causal efficacy and the fact that it abides in its own nature. The Vaibhāṣika philosopher Saṃghabhadra defines an existent as follows: "The characteristic of a real existent is that it serves as an object-domain for generating cognition." Each cognition is intentional and it has a distinctive character which is caused by the intrinsic characteristic of the object of cognition. If there is no object of cognition, there is no cognition.
Furthermore, according to Saṃghabhadra, only if there are true existent forms can there be a difference between correct and incorrect cognitions regarding material things.
Saṃghabhadra further adds that they are of two types of existents:
What exists truly and what exists conceptually, the two being designated on the basis of conventional truth and absolute truth. If, with regard to a thing, a cognition is produced without depending on anything else, this thing exists truly — e.g., rūpa, vedanā, etc. If it depends on other things to produce a cognition, then it exists conceptually/relatively — e.g., a vase, army, etc.
Furthermore, things that truly exist are also of two types: those things that just have their own nature and those things that have both their own nature and also have activities. Additionally, this last type is divided into two: "with or without function." Lastly, relative existents are also of two types, "having existence on the basis of something real or on something relative, like a vase and an army, respectively."

Arguments in favor of temporal eternalism

According to Jan Westerhoff, one reason they had for holding this theory was that moments of consciousness are intentional and thus if there are no past entities which exist, thoughts about them would be objectless and could not exist. Another argument is that to account for past actions which have effects at a later time. If an act of karma no longer exists, it is difficult, argues the Vaibhāṣika, to see how they can have fruits in the present or future. Finally, past, present and future are mutually interdependent ideas. If past and future are non-existent, argued the Vaibhāṣikas, how can one make sense of the existence of the present?
In the Samyukta-abhidharma-hrdaya, a fourth century Gandharan Sarvāstivāda text, the core Sarvāstivāda theory is defended thus:
Vasubandhu outlines the main arguments based on scripture and reason for all exists as follows:
Regarding time, for Vaibhāṣikas, it is just a superimposition on the activity of these different types of dharmas and does not exist independently. Because of this, there was a need to explain how one experiences time and change. Among the different Sarvāstivāda thinkers, there were different ideas on how dharmas change so as to give rise to the experience of time. The Mahāvibhāṣa speaks of four major theories which attempt to do this:
The positions are further outlined by Vasubandhu as follows:
  1. "The Bhadanta Dharmatrata defends change in mode of being, that is, he affirms that the three time periods, past, present, and future, are differentiated by their non-identity of existence. When a dharma goes from one time period to another its nature is not modified, but its existence is."
  2. "The Bhadanta Ghosaka defends change in characteristic, that is, the time periods differ through the difference in their characteristics. A dharma goes through the time periods. When it is past, it is endowed with past characteristics, but it is not deprived of its present and future characteristics..."
  3. "The Bhadanta Vasumitra defends change in state/condition, that is, the time periods differ through the difference of condition. A dharma, going through the time periods, having taken up a certain condition, becomes different through the difference of its condition, not through a difference in its substance. Example: a token placed on the square of ones, is called one; placed on the square of tens, ten; and placed on the square of hundreds, one hundred."
  4. "The Bhadanta Buddhadeva defends change in relativity, that is, the time periods are established through their mutual relationships. A dharma, going throughout the time periods, takes different names through different relationships, that is, it is called past, future, or present, through a relationship with what precedes and with what follows. For example, the same woman is both a daughter and a mother."
In the Abhidharmakośa, Vasubandhu argues that "the best system is that of Vasumitra". The Samyukta-abhidharma-hrdaya agrees.
Later Sarvāstivāda developed a combination of the first and third views. This can be seen in Saṃghabhadra, who argues that while a dharma's essential nature does not change, its function or activity and its existence changes:
The essential nature of a dharma remains eternally; its bhāva changes: When a saṃskṛta dharma traverses through adhvan , it gives rise to its kāritra in accordance with the pratyaya-s , without abandoning its substantial nature; immediately after this, the kāritra produced ceases. Hence it is said that the svabhāva exists eternally and yet it is not permanent, since its bhāva changes.
Thus, for Saṃghabhadra, "a dharma is present when it exercises its kāritra, future when its kāritra is not yet exercised, past when it has been exercised." The term kāritra is defined as "a dharma’s capability of inducing the production of its own next moment." When the right set of conditions come together, a dharma becomes endowed with activity. When it does not have activity, a dharma's own nature still has the capacity to causally contribute to other dharmas.

''Svabhāva'' in time

Regarding the essential nature or reality of a dharma, all Vaibhāṣika thinkers agreed that it is what remains constant and does not change as a dharma moves throughout the three times. However, as noted by K.L. Dhammajoti, this does not necessarily mean that a dharma's svabhāva "is immutable or even permanent, for a dharma’s mode of existence and its essential nature are not different, so that when the former is undergoing transformation, so is its svabhāva."
From the Vaibhāṣika perspective this is not a contradiction, since it is the same process that remains throughout time. Thus, in this particular sense, there is no change in the svabhāva or svalakṣaṇa. This is said to be the case even though a dharma is always being transformed into different modes of being. Each of these is actually a new occasion or event in a causal stream. Thus according to K.L. Dhammajoti, there is a way in which the essential natures are transformed, and yet, one can say that they remain the same ontologically. Dharmatrāta used the example of a piece of gold that is transformed into different things. While there are different entities, the essential nature of gold remains the same.
This perspective is expressed by Saṃghabhadra who argues that svabhāva is not permanent since it goes through time and its existence varies through time. Saṃghabhadra also notes that a dharma is produced by various causes, and once a dharma has ceased, it does not arise again. However, for Saṃghabhadra, one can still say that dharmas do not lose their svabhāva. He uses the example of vedanās. Even though we speak of various modes of sensation, all the types of sensation in a person's mindstream have the same nature of being sensitive phenomena. Saṃghabhadra then states:
It is not the case that since the function is different from the existence, that there can be the difference in the functions of seeing, hearing, etc. Rather, the very function of seeing, etc., is none other than the existence of the eye, etc. On account of the difference in function, there is definitely the difference in the mode of existence… Since it is observed that there are dharma‑s that co-exist as essential substances and whose essential characteristics do not differ but that have different modes of existence, we know that when dharma‑s traverse the three times, their modes of existence vary while their essential characteristics do not change.
He also states:
also have properly refuted the objection that implies the permanence of essential nature, for, while the essential nature remains always , its avasthā differs since there is change. This difference of avasthā is produced on account of conditions and necessarily stays no more than one kṣaṇa . Accordingly, the essential nature of the dharma too is impermanent, since it is not distinct from the difference . it is only in an existent dharma that changes can obtain; there cannot be change in a non-existent. In this way, therefore, we have properly established the times.
According to K.L. Dhammajoti, what the Vaibhāṣikas had in mind with this view was that even though the different dharmas in a causal series are different entities, there is an overall "individuality or integrity", and the series thus remains "dynamically identical." This is a relationship of identity-in-difference. In this sense, a svabhāva is not a static entity, it is impermanent and undergoes change and yet "ontologically it never becomes a totally different substance." Saṃghabhadra claimed that it is only when understood in this way that the doctrine of "all exists" is logically compatible with the doctrine of impermanence.

Momentariness

Orthodox Sarvāstivāda also defended the theory of moments. This doctrine held that dharmas last only for a moment, this measure of time is the smallest measure of time possible, it is described in the Samyukta-abhidharma-hrdaya as:

Theory of Causality

An important topic covered in Vaibhāṣika Abhidharma was the investigation of causes, conditions and their effects. Vaibhāṣikas used two major schemes to explain causality: the four conditions and the six causes. In this system, the arising of dharmas is totally dependent on specific causes. Causal force is what makes a dharma real and thus they are also called saṃskāras. Because of this, all dharmas belong to some kind of causal category, and are said to have causal efficacy. Indeed, it is only through examining their causes that the intrinsic nature manifests in a cognizable way. In the Vaibhāṣika system, the activities of dharmas arises through the mutual interdependence of causes. Thus, their intrinsic natures are said to be "feeble", which means they are not able to act on their own, and their activity is dependent on other dharmas.
A particularly unique feature of the Vaibhāṣika system is their acceptance of simultaneous causation. These "co-existent causes" are an important part of the Sarvāstivāda understanding of causality. It allowed them to explain their theory of direct realism, that is to say, their affirmation that we perceive real external objects. It also was used in their defense of temporal eternalism. Thus, it was central to their understanding of cause and effect. For thinkers like Saṃghabhadra, a sense organ and its object must exist at the same moment together with its effect, the perception. Thus, for a cause to be efficacious, it must exist together with its effect. This view of simultaneous causation was rejected by the Sautrāntikas, but later adopted by the Yogācāra school.

The Six Causes

Saṃghabhadra argues that even though the arising of dharmas depends on numerous conditions, the Buddha taught only four conditions in the sutras. Against the Sautrāntikas, who held that these were mere conceptual designations, Vaibhāṣikas assert that they are real existents.
The four conditions are first found in Devaśarman’s Vijñānakāya and they are:
The Sarvāstivāda also taught that there are five fruits i.e. causal effects:
The Vaibhāṣika epistemology defended a form of realism that is established through experience. Their theory of knowledge held that one could know dharmas as unique forces with unique characteristics by two means of knowledge : direct perception or inference, which relies on direct experience.
For Vaibhāṣikas like Saṃghabhadra “the characteristic of an existent is that it can serve as an object producing cognition ”. Because of this, an object of knowledge is necessarily existent, though it can be either a true existent or a conceptual existent. As Dhammajoti notes, "the possibility of knowing an object necessarily implies the true ontological status of the object."
This view was rejected by Sautrāntikas like Śrīlāta, who argued that a cognitive object could be unreal, pointing to examples such as optical illusions, dreams, the false cognition of a self or really existent person, and so on. The Vaibhāṣika response to this is that even in the case of such mistaken cognitive constructs, there is a real basis which acts as part of the causal process. As explained by Dhammajoti:
An absolute non-existent has no function whatsoever and hence can never engender a consciousness. Thus, in the case of the perception of the unreal pudgala, the perceptual object is not the pudgala which is superimposed, but the five skandha‑s which are real existents.
Furthermore, as noted by Dhammajoti: "sensory perception as a pratyakṣa experience is fully accomplished only in the second moment on recollection." This is because the external object must first be experienced by "direct perception supported by a sense faculty" before a discerning perception can arise, since the discerning perception uses the previous sense faculty perception as a cognitive support.
Vaibhāṣika defended the real existence of external objects by arguing that mental defilements arise in different ways because of the causal force of the mind's intentional object. Likewise, sensory perception is said to arise due to various causes and conditions, one of which is a real external object. According to Dhammajoti, for Vaibhāṣikas like Saṃghabhadra, "a sensory consciousness necessarily takes a physical assemblage or agglomeration of atoms. What is directly perceived is just these atoms assembled together in a certain manner, not a conceptualized object such as a jug, etc."
For Vaibhāṣika knowledge is a
caitta'' that has the distinguishing characteristic of being "understanding that is decisive or definite ". There are various kinds of knowledge, for example, dharma-knowledge, is the knowledge that realizes the true nature of dharmas, conventional-knowledge deals with conventional things and knowledge of non-arising refers to the knowledge one has when one knows nirvana has been achieved.

Defilement (''kleśa'')

The goal of Buddhism is often seen as the freedom from suffering which arises from the complete removal of all defilements. This is a state of perfection that is known by an arhat or Buddha through the "knowledge of the destruction of the outflows". Ābhidharmikas saw the Abhidharma itself, which in the highest sense is just wisdom, as the only means to end the defilements.
Kleśa is commonly defined as that which "soils" or defiles as well as that which disturbs and afflicts a psycho-physical series. Another important synonym for defilement is anuśaya, which is explained by Vaibhāṣikas as a subtle or fine dharma that adheres and grows with an object, "like the adherence of dust on a wet garment or the growth of seeds in an irrigated field". This is in contrast to other interpretations of anuśaya, such as that of the Sautrāntikas, who saw them as "seeds" of kleśas. Thus, for Vaibhāṣikas there is no such thing as a latent defilement.
The defilements are seen as the root of existence, since they produce karma, which in turn leads to further rebirths. The most fundamental defilements are known as the three unskillful roots, referring to greed, hostility and ignorance. Out of these, ignorance is the most fundamental of all. It is defined by Saṃghabhadra as "a distinct dharma which harms the capability of understanding. It is the cause of topsy-turvy views and obstructs the examination of merits and faults. With regard to dharma-s to be known it operates in the mode of disinclination, veiling the thought and thoughtconcomitants."
According to Dhammajoti, other major terms used to describe defilements are: 1. fetter ; 2. bondage ; 3. envelopment ; 4. outflow ; 5. flood ; 6. yoke ; 7. clinging ; 8. corporeal tie ; 9. hindrance. These numerous categories are used to describe various doctrinal topics and create a taxonomy of dharmas. For example, all dharmas are either with or without outflows, which are dharmas that keep sentient beings flowing on through existence and also cause impurities to flow through the sense fields.
These are also further divided into sub-categories. For example, there are three āsrava types: sensuality-outflow, existence-outflow and ignorance-outflow ; there are four clingings: sensuality-clinging, view-clinging, clinging to abstentions and vows, and Soul-theory-clinging ; and there are five hindrances: sensual-desire, malice, torpor-drowsiness, restlessness-remorse, and doubt.
For Vaibhāṣikas, the elimination of the defilements thus begins with an investigation into the nature of dharmas. This examination is carried out in various ways, such as investigating how defilements arise and grow, what its cognitive objects are, and whether a defilement is to be abandoned by insight into the four noble truths or by cultivation.
In the Vaibhāṣika system, the abandonment of a defilement is not the complete destruction of it, since all dharmas exist throughout the three times. Instead, one becomes defiled when the dharma of acquisition links one with the defilement, and one abandons the defilement when there is both the ceasing of the dharma of acquisition as well as the arising of the acquisition of disconnection. While the abandonment of a dharma happens at once and is not repeated, the acquisition of disconnection can take place over and over again, reflecting deeper and firmer spiritual progress.
This is important because as Dhammajoti notes, Vaibhāṣikas affirm that "freedom from duḥkha must be gained by gradually and systematically abandoning the defilements" and reject the view that awakening happens abruptly. There are four methods of abandoning a defilement, the first three deal with abandonment by insight :
  1. ālambana-parijñāna: Complete understanding of the nature of the object due to which the defilement arises.
  2. tadālambana-saṃkṣaya: The destruction of a defilement which is the object of another defilement along with the destruction of the latter.
  3. ālambana-prahāṇa: The abandonment of a defilement that takes as object another defilement by abandoning the latter — the object.
  4. pratipakṣodaya: The abandonment of a defilement on account of the arising of its counteragent. This is specifically applied to the defilements that are abandoned by cultivation ''.

    Karma

While the Vaibhāṣikas acknowledge the profound and ultimately inconceivable nature of karma, they still attempted to give a rational account of its basic workings and to show how it was a middle way between determinism and absolute freedom. The Mahāvibhāṣa notes that there are different but related ways in which the term karma is used. It can refer to actions in a general sense and it can refer specifically to ethical actions which have desirable or undesirable effects.
Karma is also used to refer to the actual retribution causes of actions, which according to Dhammajoti, play a crucial role "in determining the various spheres, planes and modes of birth of a sentient being’s existence and in differentiating the various types of persons with their various life-span, physical appearances, social status, etc."
It is also important to note that, karma is not the only contributing factor to rebirth, as Vasubandhu states: "It is not karma alone which is the projector of a birth." Karma is also related to the defilements since the defilements act as the generating cause and supporting condition for karma.

Classifications

There are three main types of karma: bodily, vocal and mental. Out of all the different elements of karma, it is the volitional aspect, which comprises all mental karma, that is the most central and fundamental, since it is originates and assists the other types of karma. Saṃghabhadra, citing the sutras, states that volition is karma "in the proper or specific sense inasmuch as it is the prominent cause in projecting a sentient existence."
The Vaibhāṣikas also had further classifications of the different types of karma. For example, there are:
The informative and non-informative category is particularly important. For the Vaibhāṣika, both types are real entities and are included as cetayitvā karma. Also, the nature of informative karma is material, it is the specific bodily shape at the time of the accomplishment of an action. Saṃghabhadra defends this by arguing that if all karma is mere volition, then as soon as one has the intention to kill, this is the same as commiting the deed. Vaibhāṣikas also held that non-informative karma was a kind of subtle "non-resistant" matter which preserved karmic efficacy, a view that was vigorously attacked by the Sautrāntikas.
Like other Buddhist schools, the Vaibhāṣikas taught the ten paths of karma as a major ethical guide to what should be avoided and what should be cultivated. It should be emphasized that volition remains the core of this teaching, that is, even if one avoids acting on one's harmful intentions, the intention itself remains an unskillful karma.

Karma through time

The Vaibhāṣika theory of karma is also closely related to their theory of tri-temporal existence, since karmas also exist in the past and in the future. Indeed, the efficacy of past karma is part of their argument for "all exists", since, for the Vaibhāṣika, if a past karmic retributive cause ceases to exist completely, it cannot lead to the karmic effect or fruit. As Dhammajoti explains:
At the very moment when a retributive cause arises, it determines the causal connection with the fruit-to-be; i.e., ‘it grasps the fruit’. At a subsequent time, when the necessary conditions obtain, it, although past, can causally actualize the fruit by dragging it, as it were, out of the future into the present; i.e., ‘it gives the fruit’.
This was of course rejected by the Sautrāntikas, who posited a competing theory, known as the theory of seeds, which held that a volition creates a chain of momentary dharmas called seeds, which are continuously transmitted in the mind stream until they sprout, producing the karmic effect.
Saṃghabhadra critiques this theory by pointing out that when a seed turns into a plant, there is no interruption in the process. But in the Sautrāntika view, there can be an interruption, as when a person has thoughts of a different ethical type or when they enter into meditations that completely interrupt mental activity. And since Sautrāntikas are presentists, the past karma has also ceased to exist at this point and thus cannot be a cause for its fruit.

Karmic retribution

In Vaibhāṣika Abhidharma, the nature of karmic retribution, i.e. how a person experiences the results of their actions, is not fixed and depends on different conditions, such as the spiritual status and wisdom of the person. There are six factors that effect the gravity of karmic retribution :
There are also said to be some karmas that may or may not lead to retribution at all, these are indeterminate karmas which are contrasted with determinate karmas, i.e. those that necessarily cause retribution. These indeterminate karmas can be rendered weak or fruitless through the practice of the spiritual path. The "Salt-simile sutra" is cited in support of this. Determinate karmas are particularly dark acts, such as killing one's parents, which cannot be so transformed.
Another important distinction here is that between karma that is done which refers to preparatory and principal actions, and karma that is accumulated which refers to the consecutive actions which "complete" the action. For example, one may prepare to kill someone and attempt to do so, but fail. In this sense, the action is not accumulated. Also, an action not done intentionally is not accumulated. Though the preparation is still a bad karma, it is not necessarily retributive. If however, something willed and accomplished is necessarily retributive.
Yet another key distinction is that between projecting and completing karmas. A projecting karma is a single act which is the principal cause that projects one's future existence, while completing karmas are responsible for specific experiences within that one existence, such as lifespan.
Finally, it is important to note that in this system, karma is primarily individual. That is to say, one person's karma will not cause a retribution fruit to be experienced by another person.
However, there is a karmic fruit which is experienced by a collective of individuals, which is the fruit of dominance, which affects the vitality and durability of external things, such as plants and planets. This is used to explain how, when persons do good actions, the external world is affected by the "four increases": "of lifespan, of sentient beings, of external items of utility and enjoyment, and of skillful dharma‑s." In this sense then, there is "collective karma." Thus, for the Vaibhāṣikas, the whole universe is the collective karma of all beings living in it.

Dependent Origination

The Sarvāstivāda Abhidharma interpretation of the key Buddhist doctrine of Dependent Origination focuses on how the 12 links contribute to rebirth from the perspective of three periods of existence. This is explained in the following way:
Though presented in a linear way in the form of a list, these factors are said to be mutually conditioning among each other in various interconnected ways.
Though the three life model, also called "prolonged", is the most widely used way of understanding dependent origination, Sarvāstivāda Abhidharmikas also accepted three other ways of explaining it:
The study of the nature and function of spiritual paths is important to Abhidharma. For the Vaibhāṣikas the spiritual path is a gradual process of abandoning the defilements; there is no "sudden enlightenment". The analysis of the various spiritual paths provided by the Vaibhāṣika Abhidharma correspond to the abandoning of various defilements.
The beginning of the path consists of preliminary practices: approaching "true persons", listening to the Dharma, contemplating the meaning and practicing the Dharma and what accords with the Dharma. Preparatory practices also include the observance of the ethical precepts, giving, and studying the Abhidharma.
The Mahāvibhāṣa contains the following succinct explanation of the stages leading up to stream entry:
At the beginning, because of his aspiration for the fruit of liberation, he diligently practices giving and the pure precepts ; the understanding derived from listening, the contemplation of the impure, mindfulness of breathing and the foundations of mindfulness ; and warmth, summits,receptivities and the supreme mundane dharma‑s; and the 15 moments of the path of vision. This is collectively said to be “firmly on one’s feet”.

Stages of the path

Vaibhāṣika developed an influential outline of the path to awakening, one which was later adapted and modified by the scholars of the Mahayana tradition into the schema of the "five paths" : The original Vaibhāṣika schema is divided into seven stages of preparatory effort and four stages of spiritual fruits :
The Seven
prayogas:
The four phala:
Each has two stages, the candidacy stage and the fruit stage.
In the prayoga stages, the contemplation of the four noble truths was done with knowledge that are with-outflow. Immediately after the last prayoga stage, one is able to access outflow-free knowledges, and must apply these to the noble truths. This is known as direct realization, direct spiritual insight into the intrinsic and common characteristics of the four truths. This takes 16 thought moments. Insight into the truths is achieved in two moments called "paths". Dhammajoti explains them as follows:
In the first moment, called the unhindered path, the outflow-free understanding that arises is called a receptivity to knowledge, and with this, the defilements abandonable by vision into the particular truth are abandoned. In the following moment, called the path of liberation, knowledge proper arises through the induction of which the acquisition of the cessation through deliberation of the defilements arises. In this way, for the whole contemplative process covering the sphere of sensuality followed by the two upper spheres, there arise eight receptivities and eight knowledges, all being prajñā in their intrinsic nature.

From the first moment of insight, which is the first moment of receptivitity, one is said to be an ārya, a noble being. This is because the out-flow free path has arisen in them and thus they are no longer an ordinary worldling. Also, according to this system, when one has entered into stream entry, there is no no going back, no retrogression. Regarding arhatship, some arhats can retrogress, mainly those who, due to their weak faculties, entered the path as a "pursuer through faith". Those who have sharp faculties and have studied and understood the teachings are not retrogressible, they are ‘ones liberated through wisdom’.

The three vehicles and noble beings

The Vaibhāṣika Sarvāstivādins are known to have employed schema of the Three Vehicles, which can be seen in the Mahāvibhāṣā:
  1. Śrāvakayāna – The vehicle of the disciples, who reach the attainment of an Arhat.
  2. Pratyekabuddhayāna – The vehicle of the "Solitary Buddhas".
  3. Bodhisattvayāna – The vehicle of the beings who are training to become a fully enlightened buddha.
The Vaibhāṣikas held that though arhats have been fully liberated through the removal of all defilements, their wisdom is not fully perfected and thus inferior to a Buddha's wisdom. Also, arhats have subtle traces that the defilements have left behind after they have been abandoned. Thus, for Vaibhāṣikas, arhats are said to have a certain non-defiled ignorance, which Buddhas lack. Furthermore, a Buddha has both omniscience and ‘wisdom of all modes’, i.e. a knowledge of all the spiritual paths.
The inferiority of the arhat attainment can be seen in texts such as the Sarvāstivādin Nāgadatta Sūtra, which critiques the Mahīśāsaka view of women in a narrative about a bhikṣuṇī named Nāgadatta. Here, the demon Māra takes the form of her father, and tries to convince her to work toward the lower stage of an arhat. Nāgadatta rejects this, saying, "A Buddha's wisdom is like empty space of the ten-quarters, which can enlighten innumerable people. But an Arhat's wisdom is inferior."
However, against the docetic view of the Mahāsāṃghikas, the Sarvāstivādins viewed the Buddha's physical body as being impure and improper for taking refuge in, and they instead regarded taking refuge in the Buddha as taking refuge in bodhi itself and also in the Dharmakāya.
The Sarvāstivādins also admitted the path of a bodhisattva as a valid one. References to the bodhisattva path and the practice of the six pāramitās are commonly found in Sarvāstivāda works. The Mahāvibhāṣā of the Vaibhāṣika Sarvāstivādins includes a schema of four pāramitās: generosity, discipline, energy, and wisdom, and it says that the four pāramitās and six pāramitās are essentially equivalent.