Every first-order formula is logically equivalent to some formula in prenex normal form. There are several conversion rules that can be recursively applied to convert a formula to prenex normal form. The rules depend on which logical connectives appear in the formula.
The rules for conjunction and disjunction say that and The equivalences are valid when does not appear as a free variable of ; if does appear free in, one can rename the bound in and obtain the equivalent. For example, in the language of rings, but because the formula on the left is true in any ring when the free variablex is equal to 0, while the formula on the right has no free variables and is false in any nontrivial ring. So will be first rewritten as and then put in prenex normal form.
Negation
The rules for negation say that and
Implication
There are four rules for implication: two that remove quantifiers from the antecedent and two that remove quantifiers from the consequent. These rules can be derived by rewriting the implication as and applying the rules for disjunction above. As with the rules for disjunction, these rules require that the variable quantified in one subformula does not appear free in the other subformula. The rules for removing quantifiers from the antecedent are : The rules for removing quantifiers from the consequent are:
Example
Suppose that,, and are quantifier-free formulas and no two of these formulas share any free variable. Consider the formula By recursively applying the rules starting at the innermost subformulas, the following sequence of logically equivalent formulas can be obtained: This is not the only prenex form equivalent to the original formula. For example, by dealing with the consequent before the antecedent in the example above, the prenex form can be obtained:
Intuitionistic logic
The rules for converting a formula to prenex form make heavy use of classical logic. In intuitionistic logic, it is not true that every formula is logically equivalent to a prenex formula. The negation connective is one obstacle, but not the only one. The implication operator is also treated differently in intuitionistic logic than classical logic; in intuitionistic logic, it is not definable using disjunction and negation. The BHK interpretation illustrates why some formulas have no intuitionistically-equivalent prenex form. In this interpretation, a proof of is a function which, given a concretex and a proof of, produces a concrete y and a proof of. In this case it is allowable for the value of y to be computed from the given value of x. A proof of on the other hand, produces a single concrete value of y and a function that converts any proof of into a proof of. If each x satisfying can be used to construct a y satisfying but no such y can be constructed without knowledge of such an x then formula will not be equivalent to formula. The rules for converting a formula to prenex form that do fail in intuitionistic logic are: and ; x does not appear as a free variable of in and ).