Nim


Nim is a mathematical game of strategy in which two players take turns removing objects from distinct heaps or piles. On each turn, a player must remove at least one object, and may remove any number of objects provided they all come from the same heap or pile. Depending on the version being played, the goal of the game is either to avoid taking the last object, or to take the last object.
Variants of Nim have been played since ancient times. The game is said to have originated in China—it closely resembles the Chinese game of 捡石子 jiǎn-shízi, or "picking stones"—but the origin is uncertain; the earliest European references to Nim are from the beginning of the 16th century. Its current name was coined by Charles L. Bouton of Harvard University, who also developed the complete theory of the game in 1901, but the origins of the name were never fully explained.
Nim is typically played as a misère game, in which the player to take the last object loses. Nim can also be played as a normal play game, where the player taking the last object wins. This is called normal play because the last move is a winning move in most games, even though it is not the normal way that Nim is played. In either normal play or a misère game, when the number of heaps with at least two objects is exactly equal to one, the next player who takes next can easily win. If this removes either all or all but one objects from the heap that has two or more, then no heaps will have more than one object, so the players are forced to alternate removing exactly one object until the game ends. If the player leaves an even number of non-zero heaps, the player takes last; if the player leaves an odd number of heaps, then the other player takes last.
Normal play Nim is fundamental to the Sprague–Grundy theorem, which essentially says that in normal play every impartial game is equivalent to a Nim heap that yields the same outcome when played in parallel with other normal play impartial games.
While all normal play impartial games can be assigned a Nim value, that is not the case under the misère convention. Only tame games can be played using the same strategy as misère Nim.
Nim is a special case of a poset game where the poset consists of disjoint chains.
The evolution graph of the game of Nim with three heaps is the same as three branches of the evolution graph of the Ulam-Warburton automaton.
At the 1940 New York World's Fair Westinghouse displayed a machine, the Nimatron, that played Nim. From May 11, 1940 to October 27, 1940 only a few people were able to beat the machine in that six week period; if they did they were presented with a coin that said Nim Champ. It was also one of the first ever electronic computerized games. Ferranti built a Nim playing computer which was displayed at the Festival of Britain in 1951. In 1952 Herbert Koppel, Eugene Grant and Howard Bailer, engineers from the W. L. Maxon Corporation, developed a machine weighing which played Nim against a human opponent and regularly won. A Nim Playing Machine has been described made from TinkerToy.
The game of Nim was the subject of Martin Gardner's February 1958 Mathematical Games column in Scientific American. A version of Nim is played—and has symbolic importance—in the French New Wave film Last Year at Marienbad.

Game play and illustration

The normal game is between two players and played with three heaps of any number of objects. The two players alternate taking any number of objects from any single one of the heaps. The goal is to be the last to take an object. In misère play, the goal is instead to ensure that the opponent is forced to take the last remaining object.
The following example of a normal game is played between fictional players Bob and Alice who start with heaps of three, four and five objects.
Sizes of heaps Moves
A B C

3 4 5 Bob takes 2 from A
1 4 5 Alice takes 3 from C
1 4 2 Bob takes 1 from B
1 3 2 Alice takes 1 from B
1 2 2 Bob takes entire A heap, leaving two 2s.
0 2 2 Alice takes 1 from B
0 1 2 Bob takes 1 from C leaving two 1s.
0 1 1 Alice takes 1 from B
0 0 1 Bob takes entire C heap and wins.

Winning positions

The practical strategy to win at the game of Nim is for a player to get the other into one of the following positions, and every successive turn afterwards they should be able to make one of the lower positions. Only the last move changes between misere and normal play.
2 Heaps3 Heaps4 Heaps
1 1 *1 1 1 **1 1 1 1 *
2 21 2 31 1 n n
3 31 4 51 2 4 7
4 41 6 71 2 5 6
5 51 8 91 3 4 6
6 62 4 61 3 5 7
7 72 5 72 3 4 5
8 83 4 72 3 6 7
9 93 5 62 3 8 9
4 8 124 5 6 7
4 9 134 5 8 9
5 8 13n n m m
5 9 12n n n n

* Only valid for normal play.
** Only valid for misere.
For the generalisations, n and m can be any value > 0, and they may be the same.

Mathematical theory

Nim has been mathematically solved for any number of initial heaps and objects, and there is an easily calculated way to determine which player will win and what winning moves are open to that player.
The key to the theory of the game is the binary digital sum of the heap sizes, that is, the sum neglecting all carries from one digit to another. This operation is also known as "exclusive or" or "vector addition over GF" . Within combinatorial game theory it is usually called the nim-sum, as it will be called here. The nim-sum of x and y is written to distinguish it from the ordinary sum,. An example of the calculation with heaps of size 3, 4, and 5 is as follows:
Binary Decimal

0112 310 Heap A
1002 410 Heap B
1012 510 Heap C
---
0102 210 The nim-sum of heaps A, B, and C, 3 ⊕ 4 ⊕ 5 = 2
An equivalent procedure, which is often easier to perform mentally, is to express the heap sizes as sums of distinct powers of 2, cancel pairs of equal powers, and then add what is left:
3 = 0 + 2 + 1 = 2 1 Heap A
4 = 4 + 0 + 0 = 4 Heap B
5 = 4 + 0 + 1 = 4 1 Heap C
--------------------------------------------------------------------
2 = 2 What is left after canceling 1s and 4s
In normal play, the winning strategy is to finish every move with a nim-sum of 0. This is always possible if the nim-sum is not zero before the move. If the nim-sum is zero, then the next player will lose if the other player does not make a mistake. To find out which move to make, let X be the nim-sum of all the heap sizes. Find a heap where the nim-sum of X and heap-size is less than the heap-size - the winning strategy is to play in such a heap, reducing that heap to the nim-sum of its original size with X. In the example above, taking the nim-sum of the sizes is. The nim-sums of the heap sizes A=3, B=4, and C=5 with X=2 are
The only heap that is reduced is heap A, so the winning move is to reduce the size of heap A to 1.
As a particular simple case, if there are only two heaps left, the strategy is to reduce the number of objects in the bigger heap to make the heaps equal. After that, no matter what move your opponent makes, you can make the same move on the other heap, guaranteeing that you take the last object.
When played as a misère game, Nim strategy is different only when the normal play move would leave only heaps of size one. In that case, the correct move is to leave an odd number of heaps of size one.
These strategies for normal play and a misère game are the same until the number of heaps with at least two objects is exactly equal to one. At that point, the next player removes either all or all but one objects from the heap that has two or more, so no heaps will have more than one object, the players leaves an odd number of non-zero heaps, so the other player takes last.
In a misère game with heaps of sizes three, four and five, the strategy would be applied like this:
A B C nim-sum

3 4 5 0102=210 I take 2 from A, leaving a sum of 000, so I will win.
1 4 5 0002=010 You take 2 from C
1 4 3 1102=610 I take 2 from B
1 2 3 0002=010 You take 1 from C
1 2 2 0012=110 I take 1 from A
0 2 2 0002=010 You take 1 from C
0 2 1 0112=310 The normal play strategy would be to take 1 from B, leaving an even number
heaps of size 1. For misère play, I take the entire B heap, to leave an odd
number of heaps of size 1.
0 0 1 0012=110 You take 1 from C, and lose.

Example implementation

The previous strategy for a misère game can be easily implemented.

import functools
MISERE = 'misere'
NORMAL = 'normal'
def nim:
"""Computes next move for Nim, for both game types normal and misere.
if there is a winning move:
return tuple
else:
return "You will lose :
>>> print
normal
- endgame scenarios change depending upon game type
>>> print
misere You will lose :
>>> print
misere
>>> print
normal You will lose :
>>> print
normal
"""
print
is_misere = game_type MISERE
is_near_endgame = False
count_non_0_1 = sum
is_near_endgame =
# nim sum will give the correct end-game move for normal play but
# misere requires the last move be forced onto the opponent
if is_misere and is_near_endgame:
moves_left = sum
is_odd =
sizeof_max = max
index_of_max = heaps.index
if sizeof_max 1 and is_odd:
return "You will lose :
nim_sum = functools.reduce
if nim_sum 0:
return "You will lose ::
target_size = heap ^ nim_sum
if target_size < heap:
amount_to_remove = heap - target_size
return index, amount_to_remove
if __name__ "__main__":
import doctest
doctest.testmod

Proof of the winning formula

The soundness of the optimal strategy described above was demonstrated by C. Bouton.
Theorem. In a normal Nim game, the player making the first move has a winning strategy if and only if the nim-sum of the sizes of the heaps is not zero. Otherwise, the second player has a winning strategy.
Proof: Notice that the nim-sum obeys the usual associative and commutative laws of addition and also satisfies an additional property, xx = 0.
Let x1, ..., xn be the sizes of the heaps before a move, and y1, ..., yn the corresponding sizes after a move. Let s = x1 ⊕ ... ⊕ xn and t = y1 ⊕ ... ⊕ yn. If the move was in heap k, we have xi = yi for all ik, and xk > yk. By the properties of ⊕ mentioned above, we have
t = 0 ⊕ t
= sst
= s ⊕ ⊕
= s ⊕ ⊕... ⊕
= s ⊕ 0 ⊕... ⊕ 0 ⊕ ⊕ 0 ⊕... ⊕ 0
= sxkyk

t = sxkyk.
The theorem follows by induction on the length of the game from these two lemmas.
Lemma 1. If s = 0, then t ≠ 0 no matter what move is made.
Proof: If there is no possible move, then the lemma is vacuously true. Otherwise, any move in heap k will produce t = xkyk from. This number is nonzero, since xkyk.
Lemma 2. If s ≠ 0, it is possible to make a move so that t = 0.
Proof: Let d be the position of the leftmost nonzero bit in the binary representation of s, and choose k such that the dth bit of xk is also nonzero.
Then letting yk = sxk, we claim that yk < xk: all bits to the left of d are the same in xk and yk, bit d decreases from 1 to 0, and any change in the remaining bits will amount to at most 2d−1. The first player can thus make a move by taking xkyk objects from heap k, then
t = sxkyk
= sxk
= 0.
The modification for misère play is demonstrated by noting that the modification first arises in a position that has only one heap of size 2 or more. Notice that in such a position s ≠ 0, therefore this situation has to arise when it is the turn of the player following the winning strategy. The normal play strategy is for the player to reduce this to size 0 or 1, leaving an even number of heaps with size 1, and the misère strategy is to do the opposite. From that point on, all moves are forced.

Variations

The subtraction game ''S''(1, 2, . . ., ''k'')

In another game which is commonly known as Nim, an upper bound is imposed on the number of objects that can be removed in a turn. Instead of removing arbitrarily many objects, a player can only remove 1 or 2 or... or k at a time. This game is commonly played in practice with only one heap.
Bouton's analysis carries over easily to the general multiple-heap version of this game. The only difference is that as a first step, before computing the Nim-sums, we must reduce the sizes of the heaps modulo k + 1. If this makes all the heaps of size zero, the winning move is to take k objects from one of the heaps. In particular, in ideal play from a single heap of n objects, the second player can win if and only if
This follows from calculating the nim-sequence of S,
from which the strategy above follows by the Sprague–Grundy theorem.

The 21 game

The game "21" is played as a misère game with any number of players who take turns saying a number. The first player says "1" and each player in turn increases the number by 1, 2, or 3, but may not exceed 21; the player forced to say "21" loses. This can be modeled as a subtraction game with a heap of 21–n objects. The winning strategy for the two-player version of this game is to always say a multiple of 4; it is then guaranteed that the other player will ultimately have to say 21 – so in the standard version where the first player opens with "1", they start with a losing move.
The 21 game can also be played with different numbers, like "Add at most 5; lose on 34".
A sample game of 21 in which the second player follows the winning strategy:
Player Number
1 1
2 4
1 5, 6 or 7
2 8
1 9, 10 or 11
2 12
1 13, 14 or 15
2 16
1 17, 18 or 19
2 20
1 21

The 100 game

A similar version is the "100 game": two players start from 0 and alternately add a number from 1 to 10 to the sum. The player who reaches 100 wins. The winning strategy is to reach a number in which the digits are subsequent.

A multiple-heap rule

In another variation of Nim, besides removing any number of objects from a single heap, one is permitted to remove the same number of objects from each heap.

Circular Nim

Yet another variation of Nim is 'Circular Nim', where any number of objects are placed in a circle, and two players alternately remove one, two or three adjacent objects. For example, starting with a circle of ten objects,
..........
three objects are taken in the first move
_....... _ _
then another three
_. _ _ _... _ _
then one
_. _ _ _.. _ _ _
but then three objects cannot be taken out in one move.

Grundy's game

In Grundy's game, another variation of Nim, a number of objects are placed in an initial heap, and two players alternately divide a heap into two nonempty heaps of different sizes. Thus, six objects may be divided into piles of 5+1 or 4+2, but not 3+3. Grundy's game can be played as either misère or normal play.

Greedy Nim

Greedy Nim is a variation where the players are restricted to choosing stones from only the largest pile. It is a finite impartial game. Greedy Nim Misère has the same rules as Greedy Nim, but here the last player able to make a move loses.
Let the largest number of stones in a pile be m, the second largest number of stones in a pile be n. Let pm be the number of piles having m stones, pn be the number of piles having n stones. Then there is a theorem that game positions with pm even are P positions.
This theorem can be shown by considering the positions where pm is odd. If pm is larger than 1, all stones may be removed from this pile to reduce pm by 1 and the new pm will be even. If pm = 1, there are two cases:
Thus there exists a move to a state where pm is even. Conversely, if pm is even, if any move is possible then it must take the game to a state where pm is odd. The final position of the game is even. Hence each position of the game with pm even must be a P position.

Index-''k'' Nim

A generalization of multi-heap Nim was called "Nim" or "index-k" Nim by E. H. Moore, who analyzed it in 1910. In index-k Nim, instead of removing objects from only one heap, players can remove objects from at least one but up to k different heaps. The number of elements that may be removed from each heap may be either arbitrary, or limited to at most r elements, like in the "subtraction game" above.
The winning strategy is as follows: Like in ordinary multi-heap Nim, one considers the binary representation of the heap sizes. In ordinary Nim one forms the XOR-sum of each binary digit, and the winning strategy is to make each XOR sum zero. In the generalization to index-k Nim, one forms the sum of each binary digit modulo k + 1.
Again the winning strategy is to move such that this sum is zero for every digit. Indeed, the value thus computed is zero for the final position, and given a configuration of heaps for which this value is zero, any change of at most k heaps will make the value non-zero. Conversely, given a configuration with non-zero value, one can always take from at most k heaps, carefully chosen, so that the value will become zero.

Building Nim

Building Nim is a variant of Nim where the two players first construct the game of Nim. Given n stones and s empty piles, the players alternate turns placing exactly one stone into a pile of their choice. Once all the stones are placed, a game of Nim begins, starting with the next player that would move. This game is denoted BN.

Higher dimensional Nim

n-d Nim is played on a board, where any number of continuous pieces can be removed from any hyper-row. The starting position is usually the full board, but other options are allowed.

Graph Nim

The starting board is a graph, and players take turn to remove 1, 2 or 3 adjacent vertices.

Candy Nim

Candy Nim is a version of normal play Nim, in which players tried to achieve two goals at the same time: taking the last object, and taking the maximum number of candies by the end of the game.