Morse–Kelley set theory
In the foundations of mathematics, Morse–Kelley set theory, Kelley–Morse set theory, Morse–Tarski set theory, Quine–Morse set theory or the system of Quine and Morse is a first order axiomatic set theory that is closely related to von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory. While von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory restricts the bound variables in the schematic formula appearing in the axiom schema of Class Comprehension to range over sets alone, Morse–Kelley set theory allows these bound variables to range over proper classes as well as sets, as first suggested by Quine in 1940 for his system ML.
Morse–Kelley set theory is named after mathematicians John L. Kelley and Anthony Morse and was first set out by and later in an appendix to Kelley's textbook General Topology, a graduate level introduction to topology. Kelley said the system in his book was a variant of the systems due to Thoralf Skolem and Morse. Morse's own version appeared later in his book A Theory of Sets.
While von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory is a conservative extension of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory in the sense that a statement in the language of ZFC is provable in NBG if and only if it is provable in ZFC, Morse–Kelley set theory is a proper extension of ZFC. Unlike von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory, where the axiom schema of Class Comprehension can be replaced with finitely many of its instances, Morse–Kelley set theory cannot be finitely axiomatized.
MK axioms and ontology
and MK share a common ontology. The universe of discourse consists of classes. Classes which are members of other classes are called sets. A class which is not a set is a proper class. The primitive atomic sentences involve membership or equality.With the exception of Class Comprehension, the following axioms are the same as those for NBG, inessential details aside. The symbolic versions of the axioms employ the following notational devices:
- The upper case letters other than M, appearing in Extensionality, Class Comprehension, and Foundation, denote variables ranging over classes. A lower case letter denotes a variable that cannot be a proper class, because it appears to the left of an ∈. As MK is a one-sorted theory, this notational convention is only mnemonic.
- The monadic predicate whose intended reading is "the class x is a set", abbreviates
- The empty set is defined by
- The class V, the universal class having all possible sets as members, is defined by V is also the Von Neumann universe.
A set and a class having the same extension are identical. Hence MK is not a two-sorted theory, appearances to the contrary notwithstanding.
Foundation: Each nonempty class A is disjoint from at least one of its members.
Class Comprehension: Let φ be any formula in the language of MK in which x is a free variable and Y is not free. φ may contain parameters which are either sets or proper classes. More consequentially, the quantified variables in φ may range over all classes and not just over all sets; this is the only way MK differs from NBG. Then there exists a class whose members are exactly those sets x such that comes out true. Formally, if Y is not free in φ:
Pairing: For any sets x and y, there exists a set whose members are exactly x and y.
Pairing licenses the unordered pair in terms of which the ordered pair,, may be defined in the usual way, as. With ordered pairs in hand, Class Comprehension enables defining relations and functions on sets as sets of ordered pairs, making possible the next axiom:
Limitation of Size: C is a proper class if and only if V can be mapped one-to-one into C.
The formal version of this axiom resembles the axiom schema of replacement, and embodies the class function F. The next section explains how Limitation of Size is stronger than the usual forms of the axiom of choice.
Power set: Let p be a class whose members are all possible subsets of the set a. Then p is a set.
Union: Let be the sum class of the set a, namely the union of all members of a. Then s is a set.
Infinity: There exists an inductive set y, meaning that the empty set is a member of y; if x is a member of y, then so is.
Note that p and s in Power Set and Union are universally, not existentially, quantified, as Class Comprehension suffices to establish the existence of p and s. Power Set and Union only serve to establish that p and s cannot be proper classes.
The above axioms are shared with other set theories as follows:
- ZFC and NBG: Pairing, Power Set, Union, Infinity;
- NBG : Extensionality, Foundation;
- NBG: Limitation of Size.
Discussion
MK is strictly stronger than ZFC and its conservative extension NBG, the other well-known set theory with proper classes. In fact, NBG—and hence ZFC—can be proved consistent in MK. MK's strength stems from its axiom schema of Class Comprehension being impredicative, meaning that φ may contain quantified variables ranging over classes. The quantified variables in NBG's axiom schema of Class Comprehension are restricted to sets; hence Class Comprehension in NBG must be predicative. The NBG axiom schema of Class Comprehension can be replaced with finitely many of its instances; this is not possible in MK. MK is consistent relative to ZFC augmented by an axiom asserting the existence of strongly inaccessible cardinals.
The only advantage of the axiom of limitation of size is that it implies the axiom of global choice. Limitation of Size does not appear in Rubin, Monk, or Mendelson. Instead, these authors invoke a usual form of the local axiom of choice, and an "axiom of replacement," asserting that if the domain of a class function is a set, its range is also a set. Replacement can prove everything that Limitation of Size proves, except prove some form of the axiom of choice.
Limitation of Size plus I being a set renders provable the sethood of the empty set; hence no need for an axiom of empty set. Such an axiom could be added, of course, and minor perturbations of the above axioms would necessitate this addition. The set I is not identified with the limit ordinal as I could be a set larger than In this case, the existence of would follow from either form of Limitation of Size.
The class of von Neumann ordinals can be well-ordered. It cannot be a set ; hence that class is a proper class, and all proper classes have the same size as V. Hence V too can be well-ordered.
MK can be confused with second-order ZFC, ZFC with second-order logic as its background logic. The language of second-order ZFC is similar to that of MK, and their syntactical resources for practical proof are almost identical. But the semantics of second-order ZFC are quite different from those of MK. For example, if MK is consistent then it has a countable first-order model, while second-order ZFC has no countable models.
Model theory
ZFC, NBG, and MK each have models describable in terms of V, the standard model of ZFC and the von Neumann universe. Let the inaccessible cardinal κ be a member of V. Also let Def denote the Δ0 definable subsets of X. Then:- Vκ is an intended model of ZFC;
- Def is an intended model of Mendelson's version of NBG which excludes global choice, replacing limitation of size by replacement and ordinary choice;
- Vκ+1, the power set of Vκ, is an intended model of MK.
History
The axioms in Kelley's ''General Topology''
The axioms and definitions in this section are, but for a few inessential details, taken from the Appendix to Kelley. The explanatory remarks below are not his. The Appendix states 181 theorems and definitions, and warrants careful reading as an abbreviated exposition of axiomatic set theory by a working mathematician of the first rank. Kelley introduced his axioms gradually, as needed to develop the topics listed after each instance of Develop below.Notations appearing below and now well-known are not defined. Peculiarities of Kelley's notation include:
- He did not distinguish variables ranging over classes from those ranging over sets;
- domain f and range f denote the domain and range of the function f; this peculiarity has been carefully respected below;
- His primitive logical language includes class abstracts of the form "the class of all sets x satisfying A."
I. Extent: For each x and each y, x=y if and only if for each z, when and only when
Identical to Extensionality above. I would be identical to the axiom of extensionality in ZFC, except that the scope of I includes proper classes as well as sets.
II. Classification : An axiom results if in
'α' and 'β' are replaced by variables, ' A ' by a formula Æ, and ' B ' by the formula obtained from Æ by replacing each occurrence of the variable which replaced α by the variable which replaced β provided that the variable which replaced β does not appear bound in A.
Develop: Boolean algebra of sets. Existence of the null class and of the universal class V.
III. Subsets: If x is a set, there exists a set y such that for each z, if, then
The import of III is that of Power Set above. Sketch of the proof of Power Set from III: for any class z which is a subclass of the set x, the class z is a member of the set y whose existence III asserts. Hence z is a set.
Develop: V is not a set. Existence of singletons. Separation provable.
IV. Union: If x and y are both sets, then is a set.
The import of IV is that of Pairing above. Sketch of the proof of Pairing from IV: the singleton of a set x is a set because it is a subclass of the power set of x. Then IV implies that is a set if x and y are sets.
Develop: Unordered and ordered pairs, relations, functions, domain, range, function composition.
V. Substitution: If f is a function and domain f is a set, then range f is a set.
The import of V is that of the axiom schema of replacement in NBG and ZFC.
VI. Amalgamation: If x is a set, then is a set.
The import of VI is that of Union above. IV and VI may be combined into one axiom.
Develop: Cartesian product, injection, surjection, bijection, order theory.
VII. Regularity: If there is a member y of x such that
The import of VII is that of Foundation above.
Develop: Ordinal numbers, transfinite induction.
VIII. Infinity: There exists a set y, such that and whenever
This axiom, or equivalents thereto, are included in ZFC and NBG. VIII asserts the unconditional existence of two sets, the infinite inductive set y, and the null set is a set simply because it is a member of y. Up to this point, everything that has been proved to exist is a class, and Kelley's discussion of sets was entirely hypothetical.
Develop: Natural numbers, N is a set, Peano axioms, integers, rational numbers, real numbers.
Definition: c is a choice function if c is a function and for each member x of domain c.
IX. Choice: There exists a choice function c whose domain is.
IX is very similar to the axiom of global choice derivable from Limitation of Size above.
Develop: Equivalents of the axiom of choice. As is the case with ZFC, the development of the cardinal numbers requires some form of Choice.
If the scope of all quantified variables in the above axioms is restricted to sets, all axioms except III and the schema IV are ZFC axioms. IV is provable in ZFC. Hence the Kelley treatment of MK makes very clear that all that distinguishes MK from ZFC are variables ranging over proper classes as well as sets, and the Classification schema.