Deontic logic
Deontic logic is the field of philosophical logic that is concerned with obligation, permission, and related concepts. Alternatively, a deontic logic is a formal system that attempts to capture the essential logical features of these concepts. Typically, a deontic logic uses OA to mean it is obligatory that A, and PA to mean it is permitted that A.
Etymology
The term deontic is derived from the Ancient Greek δέον déon, meaning "that which is binding or proper."Standard deontic logic
In Georg Henrik von Wright's first system, obligatoriness and permissibility were treated as features of acts. Soon after this, it was found that a deontic logic of propositions could be given a simple and elegant Kripke-style semantics, and von Wright himself joined this movement. The deontic logic so specified came to be known as "standard deontic logic," often referred to as SDL, KD, or simply D. It can be axiomatized by adding the following axioms to a standard axiomatization of classical propositional logic:In English, these axioms say, respectively:
- If it ought to be that A implies B, then if it ought to be that A, it ought to be that B;
- If A is permissible, then it is not the case that it ought not to be that A.
There are two main extensions of SDL that are usually considered. The first results by adding an alethic modal operator in order to express the Kantian claim that "ought implies can":
where. It is generally assumed that is at least a KT operator, but most commonly it is taken to be an S5 operator.
The other main extension results by adding a "conditional obligation" operator O read "It is obligatory that A given B". Motivation for a conditional operator is given by considering the following case. It seems true that the starving and poor ought to be fed. But that the starving and poor are fed implies that there are starving and poor. By basic principles of SDL we can infer that there ought to be starving and poor! The argument is due to the basic K axiom of SDL together with the following principle valid in any normal modal logic:
If we introduce an intensional conditional operator then we can say that the starving ought to be fed only on the condition that there are in fact starving: in symbols O. But then the following argument fails on the usual semantics for conditionals: from O and that A implies B, infer OB.
Indeed, one might define the unary operator O in terms of the binary conditional one O as, where stands for an arbitrary tautology of the underlying logic. Similarly Alan R. Anderson shows how to define O in terms of the alethic operator and a deontic constant s standing for some sanction :. Intuitively, the right side of the biconditional says that A's failing to hold necessarily implies a sanction.
Dyadic deontic logic
An important problem of deontic logic is that of how to properly represent conditional obligations, e.g. If you smoke, then you ought to use an ashtray. It is not clear that either of the following representations is adequate:Under the first representation it is vacuously true that if you commit a forbidden act, then you ought to commit any other act, regardless of whether that second act was obligatory, permitted or forbidden. Under the second representation, we are vulnerable to the gentle murder paradox, where the plausible statements if you murder, you ought to murder gently, you do commit murder, and to murder gently you must murder imply the less plausible statement: you ought to murder. Others argue that must in the phrase to murder gently you must murder is a mistranslation from the ambiguous English word. Interpreting must as implies does not allow one to conclude you ought to murder but only a repetition of the given you murder. Misinterpreting must as ought results in a perverse axiom, not a perverse logic. With use of negations one can easily check if the ambiguous word was mistranslated by considering which of the following two English statements is equivalent with the statement to murder gently you must murder: is it equivalent to if you murder gently it is forbidden not to murder or if you murder gently it is impossible not to murder ?
Some deontic logicians have responded to this problem by developing dyadic deontic logics, which contain binary deontic operators:
Dyadic deontic logic escapes some of the problems of standard deontic logic, but it is subject to some problems of its own.
Other variations
Many other varieties of deontic logic have been developed, including non-monotonic deontic logics, paraconsistent deontic logics, and dynamic deontic logics.History
Early deontic logic
Philosophers from the Indian Mimamsa school to those of Ancient Greece have remarked on the formal logical relations of deontic concepts and philosophers from the late Middle Ages compared deontic concepts with alethic ones.In his Elementa juris naturalis, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz notes the logical relations between the licitum, the illicitum, the debitum, the, and the indifferens are equivalent to those between the possibile, the impossibile, the necessarium, and the contingens respectively.
Mally's first deontic logic and von Wright's first ''plausible'' deontic logic
, a pupil of Alexius Meinong, was the first to propose a formal system of deontic logic in his Grundgesetze des Sollens and he founded it on the syntax of Whitehead's and Russell's propositional calculus. Mally's deontic vocabulary consisted of the logical constants U and ∩, unary connective !, and binary connectives f and ∞.Mally defined f, ∞, and ∩ as follows:
Mally proposed five informal principles:
He formalized these principles and took them as his axioms:
From these axioms Mally deduced 35 theorems, many of which he rightly considered strange. Karl Menger showed that !A ↔ A is a theorem and thus that the introduction of the ! sign is irrelevant and that A ought to be the case if A is the case. After Menger, philosophers no longer considered Mally's system viable. Gert Lokhorst lists Mally's 35 theorems and gives a proof for Menger's theorem at the under .
The first plausible system of deontic logic was proposed by G. H. von Wright in his paper Deontic Logic in the philosophical journal Mind in 1951. Since the publication of von Wright's seminal paper, many philosophers and computer scientists have investigated and developed systems of deontic logic. Nevertheless, to this day deontic logic remains one of the most controversial and least agreed-upon areas of logic.
G. H. von Wright did not base his 1951 deontic logic on the syntax of the propositional calculus as Mally had done, but was instead influenced by alethic modal logics, which Mally had not benefited from. In 1964, von Wright published A New System of Deontic Logic, which was a return to the syntax of the propositional calculus and thus a significant return to Mally's system. G. H. von Wright's adoption of the modal logic of possibility and necessity for the purposes of normative reasoning was a return to Leibniz.
Although von Wright's system represented a significant improvement over Mally's, it raised a number of problems of its own. For example, Ross's paradox applies to von Wright's deontic logic, allowing us to infer from "It is obligatory that the letter is mailed" to "It is obligatory that either the letter is mailed or the letter is burned", which seems to imply it is permissible that the letter is burned. The Good Samaritan paradox also applies to his system, allowing us to infer from "It is obligatory to nurse the man who has been robbed" that "It is obligatory that the man has been robbed". Another major source of puzzlement is Chisholm's paradox. There is no formalisation in von Wright's system of the following claims that allows them to be both jointly satisfiable and logically independent:
- It ought to be that Jones goes.
- It ought to be that if Jones goes, then he tells them he is coming.
- If Jones doesn't go, then he ought not tell them he is coming.
- Jones doesn't go.
Jørgensen's dilemma
This problem is best seen as a trilemma.
The following three claims are incompatible:
- Logical inference requires that the elements have truth-values
- Normative statements do not have truth-values
- There are logical inferences between normative statements
The reject the first premise.
They provide inference mechanism on elements without presupposing that these elements have truth-values.
Alternatively, one can deny the second premise. One way to do this is to distinguish between the norm itself and a proposition about the norm.
According to this response, only the proposition about the norm has a truth-value.
Finally, one can deny the third premise. But this is to deny that there is a logic of norms worth investigating.