In mathematics, especially in order theory, the cofinality cf of a partially ordered setA is the least of the cardinalities of the cofinal subsets of A. This definition of cofinality relies on the axiom of choice, as it uses the fact that every non-empty set of cardinal numbers has a least member. The cofinality of a partially ordered setA can alternatively be defined as the least ordinalx such that there is a function from x to A with cofinal image. This second definition makes sense without the axiom of choice. If the axiom of choice is assumed, as will be the case in the rest of this article, then the two definitions are equivalent. Cofinality can be similarly defined for a directed set and is used to generalize the notion of a subsequence in a net.
* In particular, the cofinality of any nonzero finite ordinal, or indeed any finite directed set, is 1, since such sets have a greatest element.
Every cofinal subset of a partially ordered set must contain all maximal elements of that set. Thus the cofinality of a finite partially ordered set is equal to the number of its maximal elements.
* In particular, let A be a set of size n, and consider the set of subsets of A containing no more than m elements. This is partially ordered under inclusion and the subsets with m elements are maximal. Thus the cofinality of this poset is n choose m.
The cofinality of the real numbers with their usual ordering is ℵ0, since N is cofinal in R. The usual ordering of R is not order isomorphic to c, the cardinality of the real numbers, which has cofinality strictly greater than ℵ0. This demonstrates that the cofinality depends on the order; different orders on the same set may have different cofinality.
Properties
If A admits a totally ordered cofinal subset, then we can find a subset B which is well-ordered and cofinal in A. Any subset of B is also well-ordered. Two cofinal subsets of B with minimal cardinality need not be order isomorphic But cofinal subsets of B with minimal order type will be order isomorphic.
Cofinality of ordinals and other well-ordered sets
The cofinality of an ordinal α is the smallest ordinal δ which is the order type of a cofinal subset of α. The cofinality of a set of ordinals or any other well-ordered set is the cofinality of the order type of that set. Thus for a limit ordinal α, there exists a δ-indexed strictly increasing sequence with limit α. For example, the cofinality of ω² is ω, because the sequence ω·m tends to ω²; but, more generally, any countable limit ordinal has cofinality ω. An uncountable limit ordinal may have either cofinality ω as does ωω or an uncountable cofinality. The cofinality of 0 is 0. The cofinality of any successor ordinal is 1. The cofinality of any nonzero limit ordinal is an infinite regular cardinal.
Regular and singular ordinals
A regular ordinal is an ordinal which is equal to its cofinality. A singular ordinal is any ordinal which is not regular. Every regular ordinal is the initial ordinal of a cardinal. Any limit of regular ordinals is a limit of initial ordinals and thus is also initial but need not be regular. Assuming the axiom of choice, is regular for each α. In this case, the ordinals 0, 1,,, and are regular, whereas 2, 3,, and ωω·2 are initial ordinals which are not regular. The cofinality of any ordinal α is a regular ordinal, i.e. the cofinality of the cofinality of α is the same as the cofinality of α. So the cofinality operation is idempotent.
Cofinality of cardinals
If κ is an infinite cardinal number, then cf is the least cardinal such that there is an unbounded function from cf to κ; cf is also the cardinality of the smallest set of strictly smaller cardinals whose sum is κ; more precisely That the set above is nonempty comes from the fact that i.e. the disjoint union of κ singleton sets. This implies immediately that cf ≤ κ. The cofinality of any totally ordered set is regular, so one has cf = cf. Using König's theorem, one can prove κ < κcf and κ < cf for any infinite cardinal κ. The last inequality implies that the cofinality of the cardinality of the continuum must be uncountable. On the other hand, the ordinal number ω being the first infinite ordinal, so that the cofinality of is card =. Therefore, Generalizing this argument, one can prove that for a limit ordinal δ On the other hand, if the axiom of choice holds, then for a successor or zero ordinal δ