Cauchy surface


In the mathematical field of Lorentzian geometry, a Cauchy surface is a certain kind of submanifold of a Lorentzian manifold. In the application of Lorentzian geometry to the physics of general relativity, a Cauchy surface is usually interpreted as defining an "instant of time"; in the mathematics of general relativity, Cauchy surfaces are important in the formulation of the Einstein equations as an evolutionary problem.
They are named for French mathematician Augustin Louis Cauchy due to their relevance for the Cauchy problem of general relativity.

Informal introduction

Although it is usually phrased in terms of general relativity, the formal notion of a Cauchy surface can be understood in familiar terms. Suppose that humans can travel at a maximum speed of 20 miles per hour. This places constraints, for any given person, upon where they can reach by a certain time. For instance, it is impossible for a person who is in Mexico at 3 o'clock to arrive in Libya by 4 o'clock; however it is possible for a person who is in Manhattan at 1 o'clock to reach Brooklyn by 2 o'clock, since the locations are ten miles apart. So as to speak semi-formally, ignore time zones and travel difficulties, and suppose that travelers are immortal beings who have lived forever.
The system of all possible ways to fill in the four blanks in
defines the notion of a causal structure. A Cauchy surface for this causal structure is a collection of pairs of locations and times such that, for any hypothetical traveler whatsoever, there is exactly one location and time pair in the collection for which the traveler was at the indicated location at the indicated time.
There are a number of uninteresting Cauchy surfaces. For instance, one Cauchy surface for this causal structure is given by considering the pairing of every location with the time of 1 o'clock, since any hypothetical traveler must have been at one specific location at this time; furthermore, no traveler can be at multiple locations at this time. By contrast, there cannot be any Cauchy surface for this causal structure that contains both the pair and since there are hypothetical travelers that could have been in Manhattan at 1 o'clock and Brooklyn at 2 o'clock.
There are, also, some more interesting Cauchy surfaces which are harder to describe verbally. One could define a function τ from the collection of all locations into the collection of all times, such that the gradient of τ is everywhere less than 1/20 hours per mile. Then another example of a Cauchy surface is given by the collection of pairs
The point is that, for any hypothetical traveler, there must be some location which the traveler was at at time ; this follows from the intermediate value theorem. Furthermore, it is impossible that there are two locations and and that there is some traveler who is at at time and at at time, since by the mean value theorem they would at some point have had to travel at speed, which must be larger than "20 miles per hour" due to the gradient condition on τ: a contradiction.
The physical theories of special relativity and general relativity define causal structures which are schematically of the above type, with the exception that locations and times are not cleanly separable from one another. Hence one can speak of Cauchy surfaces for these causal structures as well.

Mathematical definition and basic properties

Let be a Lorentzian manifold. One says that a map is an inextendible differentiable timelike curve in if:
A subset of is called a Cauchy surface if every inextendible differentiable timelike curve in has exactly one point of intersection with ; if there exists such a subset, then is called globally hyperbolic.
The following is automatically true of a Cauchy surface :
It is hard to say more about the nature of Cauchy surfaces in general. The example of
as a Cauchy surface for Minkowski space makes clear that, even for the "simplest" Lorentzian manifolds, Cauchy surfaces may fail to be differentiable everywhere, and that the homeomophism may fail to be even a -diffeomorphism. However, the same argument as for a general Cauchy surface shows that if a Cauchy surface is a -submanifold of, then the flow of a smooth timelike vector field defines a -diffeomorphism, and that any two Cauchy surfaces which are both -submanifolds of will be -diffeomorphic.
Furthermore, at the cost of not being able to consider arbitrary Cauchy surface, it is always possible to find smooth Cauchy surfaces :

Cauchy developments

Let be a time-oriented Lorentzian manifold. One says that a map is an past-inextendible differentiable causal curve in if:
One defines a future-inextendible differentiable causal curve by the same criteria, with the phrase "as decreases to " replaced by "as increases to ". Given a subset of, the future Cauchy development of is defined to consist of all points of such that if is any past-inextendible differentiable causal curve such that for some in, then there exists some in with. One defies the past Cauchy development by the same criteria, replacing "past-inextendible" with "future-inextendible".
Informally:
The Cauchy development is the union of the future Cauchy development and the past Cauchy development.

Discussion

When there are no closed timelike curves, and are two different regions. When the time dimension closes up on itself everywhere so that it makes a circle, the future and the past of are the same and both include. The Cauchy surface is defined rigorously in terms of intersections with inextensible curves in order to deal with this case of circular time. An inextensible curve is a curve with no ends: either it goes on forever, remaining timelike or null, or it closes in on itself to make a circle, a closed non-spacelike curve.
When there are closed timelike curves, or even when there are closed non-spacelike curves, a Cauchy surface still determines the future, but the future includes the surface itself. This means that the initial conditions obey a constraint, and the Cauchy surface is not of the same character as when the future and the past are disjoint.
If there are no closed timelike curves, then given a partial Cauchy surface and if, the entire manifold, then is a Cauchy surface. Any surface of constant in Minkowski space-time is a Cauchy surface.

Cauchy horizon

If then there exists a Cauchy horizon between and regions of the manifold not completely determined by information on. A clear physical example of a Cauchy horizon is the second horizon inside a charged or rotating black hole. The outermost horizon is an event horizon, beyond which information cannot escape, but where the future is still determined from the conditions outside. Inside the inner horizon, the Cauchy horizon, the singularity is visible and to predict the future requires additional data about what comes out of the singularity.
Since a black hole Cauchy horizon only forms in a region where the geodesics are outgoing, in radial coordinates, in a region where the central singularity is repulsive, it is hard to imagine exactly how it forms. For this reason, Kerr and others suggest that a Cauchy horizon never forms, instead that the inner horizon is in fact a spacelike or timelike singularity. The inner horizon corresponds to the instability due to mass inflation.
A homogeneous space-time with a Cauchy horizon is anti-de Sitter space.